Summary
Contents
Subject index
Building on the success of the bestselling The SAGE Handbook of Grounded Theory (2007), this title provides a much-needed and up-to-date overview, integrating some revised and updated chapters with new ones exploring recent developments in grounded theory and research methods in general. The highly acclaimed editors have once again brought together a team of key academics from a wide range of disciplines, perspectives and countries. This is a method-defining resource for advanced students and researchers across the social sciences. Chapters are arranged around the following parts: Part One: The Grounded Theory Method: 50 Years On; Part Two: Theories and Theorizing in Grounded Theory; Part Three: Grounded Theory in Practice; Part Four: Reflections on Using and Teaching Grounded Theory; Part Five: GTM and Qualitative Research Practice; Part Six: GT Researchers and Methods in Local and Global Worlds
Grounded Theory's Best Kept Secret: The Ability to Build Theory
Grounded Theory's Best Kept Secret: The Ability to Build Theory
Introduction
As a lifelong passionate adherent of grounded theory method (GTM), and having watched GTM become more and more popular, and relevant, in a range of academic disciplines, I have one outstanding question. Why is it that the recommendations of Glaser and Strauss (1967) for moving from substantive to formal theory are not more widely discussed? If we take as our starting point Glaser and Strauss's definition of substantive theory, which is one developed for a substantive, or empirical area of inquiry, it is clear that the majority of theories generated using GTM fall into this definition. Why is it that we do not then attempt to build formal theory, which Glaser and Strauss define as one developed for a formal, or conceptual area of inquiry? Especially as Glaser and Strauss point out that substantive and formal theories exist on distinguishable levels of generality, and that each type can shade at points into the other?
Given an ongoing concern about theory building in many newer academic disciplines (Weber 2003; Lester 2005; Oswick, Fleming and Hanlon 2011; Johnson, Eksted and Jacobson, 2012), which centre on those disciplines’ ability to build formal theory, it seems timely to examine this question in more detail, and to explore GTM's undoubted contribution to a larger theory building effort in academic disciplines. While some social sciences have a long history of abstract theorizing (e.g., Stinchcombe 1991), many newer disciplines do not. Even in those disciplines, the advice of Glaser and Strauss (1967) with regard to theoretical sampling, looking at dissimilar and similar groups with unsaturated and saturated categories, seems rarely acted upon, presumably because of some difficulties operationalizing the advice. I remain convinced that this advice gives us valuable guidance when building theory, because it gives us advice on extending the scope and generality of a theory, which in turn can lead us to building bigger, more formal theories.
The rest of this chapter looks at theory building debates in the newer academic disciplines and considers GTMs contribution to the idea of theory. I then look at Glaser and Strauss's (1967) recommendations about theory building in detail, with special reference to minimizing and maximizing group differences. What might those recommendations tell us in 2017? What might we learn when we apply those recommendations?
Theory and Grounded Theory
Glaser and Strauss (1967) set out the role of theory in sociology as both enabling prediction and explanation of behaviour, and also as ‘being readily understandable to sociologists of any viewpoint, to students and to significant laymen'. They also state that the theory needs to be clear enough to be operationalized in quantitative studies where appropriate. They were also concerned with issues of fit of the theory, by which they meant that the theory must be able to explain the phenomena, and not be forced on to the phenomena as an explanation. Above all, they pointed out that enduring theories are based on data, are grounded in that data, and cannot easily be refuted (Glaser and Strauss 1967). They also made the important point that how theories are assessed is also dependent on how the theory was generated.
If we fast forward to recent debates about theory in management, and in information systems, we see some similar themes. For instance, Corley and Gioia (2011) are as concerned with the utility of a management theory as its originality. Oswick, Fleming and Hanlon (2011) wonder if theory borrowing from other disciplines constrains the development of new and indigenous theories. This also raises issues of fit of those borrowed theories, and whether those theories are adequately grounded in data from their home discipline. In software engineering, the question has been raised about the absence of theories in the discipline (Johnson et al. 2012), and the utility of theories to the discipline.
In information systems, a lively debate about the importance of theory to the discipline occurred in 2014. Avison and Malaurent (2014) railed against what they saw as a fetishing of theory in the discipline, the fact that various theories fell in and out of favour, and again, raised questions about the fit of borrowed theories. Their piece was accompanied by several commentaries from Lee (2014), Markus (2014), and Gregor (2014). One striking agreement among the commentaries was that there was indeed a lack of consensus about what a theory is.
Overall then, we see in these debates a lack of consensus about what theory is, and also a concern about the fit of theories imported from older reference disciplines. While the first is probably attributable to the newness of some of these disciplines, it is interesting to note that there are also concerns about fit and groundedness of theories, whether imported from outside the discipline (fit) or within the discipline (groundedness).
Gregor (2006) is quoted in a number of these debates, and her definition of theory bears repeating here because it is both broad and helpful. She defines theories as ‘abstract entities that aim to describe, explain, and enhance understanding of the world and in some cases, to provide predictions of what will happen in the future and to give a basis for intervention and action’ (p. 616). She further categorizes theories into those that analyze and describe (but do not contain causal relationships), theories for explanation (but with no testable propositions), theories for prediction (testable propositions but no causal explanations), and theories for both explanation and prediction. She also adds theories for design and action, which can be seen as more specific to information systems and software engineering.
Gregor also defines the components of all theories as containing a means of representation, constructs, statements of relationship, and scope. It is useful to consider how these conventional components compare to the grounded theory process of theory building, simply because it seems rarely that grounded theory is discussed in the same way as theory in general – yet the components are the same, as Table 4.1 comparing Gregor's components to GTM indicates.
Table 4.1 Comparing Gregor (2006) components to grounded theory building (Urquhart, 2013) | ||
---|---|---|
Theory Component | Definition | In Grounded Theory |
Means of representation | The theory must be represented physically in some way: in words, mathematical terms, symbolic logic, diagrams, tables or graphically. | Theories in GTM are often represented by a narrative framework, diagrams or statements of hypotheses. |
Constructs | These refer to the phenomena of interest in the theory (Dubin's ‘units’). All of the primary constructs in the theory should be well defined. Many different types of constructs are possible: for example, observational (real) terms, theoretical (nominal) terms and collective terms. | In GTM, the aim is to get to one to two core categories or constructs. This makes for a more parsimonious and coherent theory. All the constructs in a grounded theory are grounded in data, which can be equated to observational (real) terms. |
Statements of relationship | These show relationships among the constructs. Again, these may be of many types: associative, compositional, unidirectional, bidirectional, conditional, or causal. The nature of the relationship specified depends on the purpose of the theory. Very simple relationships can be specified: for example, ‘x is a member of class A.' | In GTM, because the theory is often (but not always) based on qualitative data, relationships are not often described in mathematical terms. There is a lot of guidance in GTM about the sort of relationships that are possible between constructs, in the form of coding families (Glaser 1978) and a coding paradigm (Corbin and Strauss 2008) |
Scope | The scope is specified by the degree of generality of the statements of relationships (signified by modal qualifiers such as ‘some’, ‘many’, ‘all’ and ‘never’) and statements of boundaries showing the limits of generalizations. | GTM aims to produce substantive theories which pertain to the area being investigated. The scope and generalizability can be extended by theoretical sampling (Glaser 1978). The substantive theory can and should be engaged with existing theories – in grounded theory, existing theories can also be seen as slices of data which help build the theory. |
A few points in the above table bear further discussion. First, and most importantly, the constructs in a grounded theory are grounded in data. Second, the founding fathers of grounded theory knew that a parsimonious theory was important – hence the recommendation that one or two ‘core’ categories (or constructs) should make up a grounded theory. This recommendation helps to raise the level of the theory and widen its potential scope. Third, grounded theories rarely have relationships described in mathematical terms, because they are grounded (usually)1 in qualitative data. That said, it is entirely possible to generate propositions about causal relationships in a grounded theory. If we look at the range of academic theories available to us, there are many different relationships represented in theories. For instance, in structuration theory, Giddens (1984) posits that social systems are created and reproduced by an inseparable duality of structure and agency. Theories like structuration theory are of course precisely the sort of ‘grand’ armchair theories that Glaser and Strauss (1967) felt did not provide sufficient theory for new areas, or simply did not work. Interestingly, Giddens did not think that his theory should be used for guiding the practice of research, but rather as a sensitizing device, which is entirely reasonable, as it can be seen as a ‘grand’ or formal theory.2
This brings us to the final point in Table 4.1, which is the issue of scope. The inevitable consequence of a grounded theory is that it tends to be a substantive theory, pertaining to the area being investigated, because if the theory needs to be grounded in data, it will naturally limit the scope of the theory to what can be observed in a single study. It is this issue of scope – and the associated boundary conditions and context – that seem to be less discussed in the literature. While in the physical sciences, boundary conditions are typically solutions expressed as equations, in the social sciences, these conditions are more likely to be boundaries of race, gender and class – and the truly universal theories might transcend these boundaries (Spatz and Kardas 2008). Davison and Martinsons (2016) have discussed the issue of theory scope in information systems, asking to what extent are the findings of a study strictly limited to the original context, and the importance of boundary conditions. Within grounded theory, there is a degree of clarity around the issue of scope, because it is clear that the scope of the theory can be extended by following the advice on theoretical sampling. The next sections look at Glaser and Strauss's definitions of substantive and formal theory, then examine their recommendations on moving substantive theory to formal theory, using theoretical sampling.
Defining Substantive and Formal Theory
Glaser and Strauss (1967) define substantive theory as ‘that developed for a substantive, or empirical area of sociological inquiry’ (p. 32). They define formal theory ‘that developed for a formal, or conceptual area of sociological inquiry’ (p. 32). They are careful to say that both types of theory can be considered middle-range and are not all-inclusive ‘grand theories'. Glaser and Strauss point out that substantive and formal theories only differ in terms of the degree of generality – that is, the scope of the theory. Formal theory is created by comparative analysis among different kinds of substantive cases. So, gradually the scope is increased, by different contexts and boundary conditions, represented by different substantive cases.
They suggest that, for substantive theory, the theorist can select groups from the same substantive class, regardless of where they are found (p. 53). They give the example of comparing an ‘emergency ward’ to all kinds of medical wards, in all kinds of hospitals, in all countries. If, however, one was to progress towards a formal theory, they suggest that it would be useful to see the emergency ward as a subclass of emergency organizations.
So let us look more deeply at the definitions of substantive and formal theory. One key difference is that formal theory categories are not underpinned by high empirical content,3 despite the fact that they have their origin in empirical data. For the purpose of Table 4.2, categories can also be seen as constructs, as defined by Gregor (2006). In grounded theory, the aim is to get to one or two core categories for a parsimonious theory (Glaser 1978; Strauss 1987). This helps the researcher to get to a reasonable level of abstraction, and mitigates against having too many low-level categories, sometimes an inevitable consequence of detailed line-by-line coding. Importantly, it helps the researcher to pull together and integrate the theory around one central concern. In turn, those core categories are underpinned by lower level categories that are firmly grounded in the data.
Table 4.2 Considering the differences between substantive and formal theory | ||
---|---|---|
Substantive Theory | Formal Theory | |
Categories | One or two core categories, underpinned by many instances in the data (high empirical content). | Underpinned by very few instances in the data. The categories that help build those formal categories, however, are underpinned by data. The formal theory category or construct is usually abstract, e.g., structure, process, role, identity, network, social capital. |
Relationships (Theoretical Codes) | Ideas for the relationships come from coding families or other theories, in line with theoretical sensitivity. Those relationships are ‘grounded’ in the data, to the extent that they are evidenced in theoretical memos and write-ups of the research. | Often the relationships or underlying mechanisms are unique – this is what distinguishes a formal theory. Again, the relationships or mechanisms will often be underpinned by empirics at the lower level. |
Scope | Scope is limited to the substantive (empirical) area of inquiry and pertains to the area being investigated. | Scope is extended by comparative analysis between different types of substantive cases. |
As the scope of a substantive theory is extended towards a formal one, category or construct names by necessity become simpler, and more abstract, because that construct has to apply to a large number of substantive cases.
Relationships between constructs or categories in grounded theory are named ‘theoretical codes’ by Glaser (1978) in his famed book Theoretical Sensitivity. The idea of theoretical sensitivity, articulated in the 1967 book, is that the grounded theorist has to be sufficiently aware of theories, and how they are constructed, in order to be able to construct their own. Glaser proposed 18 ‘coding families’ in Theoretical Sensitivity that give inspiration for relationships between categories. These families (now totalling 41, with the families proposed in Glaser (2005)) are themselves often inspired by how other theories conceptualize phenomena. A few examples of theoretical families are given in Table 4.3.
Table 4.3 Examples of Theoretical Families from Glaser (1978, 2005), adapted from Urquhart (2013) | |
---|---|
Family | Comment |
The 6 Cs – Causes, Contexts, Contingencies, Consequences, Covariances and Conditions | This basic coding family, together with family 5, the Strategy Family, was adapted by (Strauss and Corbin 1990) as their coding paradigm of ‘Causal Conditions, Context, Intervening Conditions, Action/Interaction Strategies and Consequences'. |
Process – Stages, staging, phases, phasing, progresssions, passages, gradations, transititions, steps, ranks, careers, ordering, trajectories, chains, sequencings, etc. | Glaser remarks that a process should have at least two stages. |
The Dimension Family – Dimensions, elements, division, piece of, properties of, facet, slice, sector, portion, segment, part, aspect, section | As Glaser says, the more we learn of a category, the more we see of its dimensions. Of all theoretical codes, this is one that all researchers are likely to use. It is also important to realize that, when theorizing, that we can privilege one dimension over another – it can become a full-blown category. |
The Type Family – Type, form, kinds, styles, classes, genre | Glaser says while dimensions divide up the whole, types show variation in the whole. So, for instance, you might have a number of styles of introducing a problem in a conversation. |
The Strategy Family – Strategies, tactics, mechanisms, managed, way, manipulation, manoeuvrings, dealing with, handling, techniques, ploys, means, goals, arrangements, dominating, positioning | The Strauss and Corbin (1990) coding paradigm seems to be a mixture of this family and the first family. |
Moment capture, when a quick intervention is critical to causing an optimal outcome, e.g., closing a deal | This is a new theoretical code introduced in the 2005 book. |
Frames, which are excavated through discourse patterns and are socio-cultural in nature | Also in the 2005 book, and based on communication theory. |
Causal family, a relative of the 6Cs family. This includes several aspects: (1) Bias random walk, (2) Amplifying causal looping, (3) Conjectural causation, (4) Repetitive causal reproductions, (5) Equifinality, (6) Reciprocal causation, (7) Triggers, (8) Causal paths, (9) Perpetual causal looping |
|
Of course, there is also guidance on relating categories in the Straussian version of grounded theory. Strauss in 1987 proposed a coding paradigm of conditions, consequences, interactions, strategies and consequences, using a procedure he named ‘axial coding'. He says the purpose of this element of axial coding is to ‘hypothesize about conditions, consequences, interactions, strategies and consequences’, that is, to think about how the categories relate. Later, Strauss and Corbin (1990) published a further coding paradigm, which prompted the now famous dispute between Glaser and Strauss. It is interesting to note, however, that the strictures about this paradigm moved from mandatory to optional, over time. Table 4.4 explains the evolution of the coding paradigm.
Table 4.4 The evolving nature of the Straussian coding paradigm (adapted from Urquhart 2013) | |
---|---|
Coding Paradigm | Comment on evolving use of paradigm |
Conditions, consequences, interactions, strategies and consequences (Strauss 1987) | In the 1987 book, it is clear that the coding paradigm is not an optional part of coding. Researchers are told to ‘follow the coding paradigm’ p. 81. |
Causal Conditions, Context, Intervening Conditions, Action/Interaction, Strategies and Consequences (Strauss and Corbin 1990) | In the 1990 book the paradigm is modified to include different types of conditions and actions. |
Conditions (causal, intervening, and contextual), Actions/Interactions (strategic or routine tactics), Consequences (immediate, cumulative, reversible, foreseen or unseen) (Strauss and Corbin 1998) | In the 1998 book, conditions are clustered together, strategies are clustered under actions and consequences elaborated on. |
Conditions, interactions and emotions, consequences (Corbin and Strauss 2008) | In the 2008 book, the paradigm loses its prominence and is presented as an optional analytic tool for novice researchers. That said, the conditional/consequence matrix, used in previous editions to think about relationships between micro and macro conditions, now has a more central place in coding. |
Moving to the question of scope, Glaser and Strauss (1967) distinguish between scope of the population covered by the theory and the conceptual level of the theory (p. 52). So for a substantive theory, different groups would be selected of exactly the same substantive type – they give the example of federal bookkeeping departments. However, if the aim is to progress to formal theory, increasingly dissimilar – and larger – groups need to be selected. The key sentences in the 1967 book are as follows:
when the sociologist's purpose is to discover formal theory, he [sic] will definitely select dissimilar, substantive groups from the larger class, while increasing his theory's scope. And he will also find himself comparing groups that seem to be non-comparable on the substantive level, but that on the formal level are conceptually comparable. … For example, while fire departments and emergency wards are substantially dissimilar, their conceptual comparability is still readily apparent … it must be explained on a higher conceptual level.’ (p. 54) (author's emphasis)
Clearly, Glaser and Strauss considered in great detail, from the beginning, the differences between substantive and formal theory, and how to move from one to the other, from a practical point of view. The next section discusses their recommendations for theoretical sampling, which are rarely discussed in the grounded theory literature, despite the undoubted insights they give us for the theory-building process.
Glaser and Strauss's Recommendations for Building Theory Using Theoretical Sampling
It is very clear that Glaser and Strauss were engaged from the outset with practical considerations for building theory – for them, the key issue of what data to collect next was always controlled by the emerging theory. The great contribution of their chapter on theoretical sampling in the 1967 book was their assertion that the selection of comparison groups gave control over two aspects of the developing theory – first, conceptual level, and second, population scope. This is expressed in a table on p. 58 of the book, reproduced in this section as Table 4.5, that shows the consequences of minimizing and maximizing differences in groups, and considering the variations within the data of those groups. Obviously, variations in the data are expressed by variations in categories.
Table 4.5 Consequences of minimizing and maximizing differences in comparison groups for generation of theory (Glaser and Strauss, 1967, p. 58) | ||
---|---|---|
Group Differences | Data on Category | |
Similar | Diverse | |
Minimized | Maximum similarity in data leads to:
| Identifying/developing fundamental differences under which category and hypothesis vary. |
Maximized | Identifying/developing fundamental uniformities of greatest scope. | Maximum diversity in data quickly forces:
|
For Glaser and Strauss, the purpose of selecting groups is not about comparisons between and inside substantive groups, useful though that may be. Their criteria are ‘theoretical purpose and relevance – not of structural circumstance’ (p. 48).
Glaser and Strauss also lay great stress on either maximizing or minimizing differences between groups to control ‘theoretical relevance’ (p. 55) of data collection. They also point out that this then has a bearing on categories. For instance, if a similar group is chosen, many more instances of a category will be collected, while important differences might be spotted that were not noticed in earlier data collection. This is important for establishing the properties of a particular category, and Glaser and Strauss suggest that these properties are established before differences in groups are maximized.
When maximizing differences between groups, data in a particular category will vary. This allows the researcher to think about the ‘strategic similarities’ between groups, which give the uniformities of scope within the theory. They state that maximizing ‘brings out the widest possible coverage on ranges, continua, degrees, types, uniformities, variations, causes, conditions, consequences, probabilities of relationships, strategies, process, structural mechanisms, and so forth, all necessary for elaboration of the theory’ (p. 57). We can see here too an early reference to theoretical coding (Glaser 1978) and a recognition that a widening of scope means that relationships between constructs have to be reconsidered. They summarize their recommendations in the table that is reproduced here (Table 4.5).
Another way of thinking about this table is that its key contribution falls into two areas. First, it helps us see that maximizing differences between groups helps us extend the scope of the theory we are working on. Second, we can raise the conceptual level of our substantive theory by considering the categories themselves. In particular, we can consider the unsaturated categories in our analysis as a promising avenue to raise the conceptual level of the theory, by guiding us to more interesting groups. The fascinating thing about this table is that it draws attention not only to issues of scope, but issues of the data, as expressed by the categories themselves, and how considering categories can improve the quality and conceptual level of the theory.
While Eisenhardt (1989) popularized theoretical sampling for group differences, she did not consider theoretical sampling of concepts in the same way as suggested above. However, she talked about within-case comparison based on categories, which can be seen as a variation of sampling for concepts in the data. The differences in strategy between grounded theorists and mainstream qualitative researchers can perhaps be seen as a consequence of different methodologies for theory building – Eisenhardt (1989) used cases, while grounded theory methodology relies upon slices of data. So, how might these recommendations for theoretical sampling, as suggested by Glaser and Strauss, be carried out? What happens if we try to follow what Table 4.5 suggests?
Enacting the Recommendations for Theoretical Sampling
In Vaast and Urquhart (2017), I briefly discuss what Glaser and Strauss's advice on theoretical sampling might mean in practice for the generation of social media theory, and use the example of Facebook statuses. In this section, I expand in detail on that example, and the steps of theory building that I believe are implied by Table 4.5, in order for us to explore what can be learned from those recommendations.
Glaser and Strauss state that, at the beginning of generating a substantive theory, differences should be minimized in comparative groups. We can choose to minimize or maximize differences in groups along several dimensions, such as age, country, language, political affiliation, and so on. Maximizing those differences helps use theorize on relationships, conditions, patterns and mechanisms (Glaser and Strauss 1967, p. 57). In our Facebook example explained below, we may wish to look at slices of data from other online sources, such as personal blogs, Twitter feeds, or how a person responds to other comments from people below the line (BTL) when commenting on a news article. The theoretical sampling and choice of data slices depends on how the theory develops. It is important to realize that the motivations for theoretical sampling are theoretically motivated; it is not a question of simply verifying the category in various populations. How might we operationalize the advice from Glaser and Strauss on theoretical sampling, and how does it help the development of a theory? Each step in the example is cross referenced to Table 4.6 below.
Table 4.6 Example of theory building using Glaser and Strauss's recommendations for comparison groups

Step 0
Let us imagine we are trying to understand how people use Facebook. Suppose we start with a group of individuals aged 18–25, based in the UK, who use Facebook. By coding their Facebook statuses, we can see that there are many instances of people actively managing their Facebook statuses. Those statuses are chosen, or curated, to give the best possible impression of that person's life and circumstances. We draw this conclusion from the data because there are very few statuses that do not portray the status owner as someone who is successful, surrounded by friends, and enjoying travel. We decide to call this concept or code ‘curating'. At the same time, we notice another interesting, minority use of Facebook status – a very personalized status that seems to be aimed at only a few people who might understand it. This concept we choose to call ‘personalizing'. At this point, then, we have a choice whether to pursue the theory development via saturated or unsaturated concepts (Lehmann 2010). What should we do next?
We can base our theoretical sampling on either ‘curation’ – what we could call maximum similarity in data, or ‘personalizing’, what we could call a fundamental difference in the data as to how people approach their Facebook statuses. In this example, we first choose to pursue the unsaturated concept ‘personalizing’, in order to learn more about the category, and proceed to Step 1.
Step 1
We would then sample a new Facebook group, of the same age, 18–25, in the same country, for the unsaturated concept of Personalizing. Thus group differences are minimized (it is a similar group) but we are pursuing diverse concepts in the data.
Our slices of data would actively seek out statuses that are Personalizing, for the purpose of learning more about this particular category. This will quickly fill out the category and help us understand how it might vary in different circumstances. Obviously, both ‘Curating’ and ‘Personalizing’ could be subsumed into a higher level concept of, say, ‘Impression Management’ as the theory increases in scope, and we could probably expect new categories to emerge, which can be aspects of ‘Impression Management'.
Step 2
We could then proceed to maximize group differences by sampling different age groups, and different countries, in order to deepen the theory and ‘identify the fundamental uniformities of greatest scope'. In this stage, we will be paying attention to the saturated concepts of curating, and possibly personalizing. This will further fill out the category ‘Impression Management’, which consists, at present of curating and personalizing, and perhaps other types of Impression Management discovered in Step 1. So, depending on how the theory is developing and the different properties of ‘Impression Management’, it might be apposite to sample a Facebook group that is older, or the same age range in a different country, so see if the categories hold true in a different culture. We could also consider whether membership of various Facebook groups has any sway on Impression Management. Thus, the theory is increasing in depth in this stage. Impression Management is also a category that is quite abstract, which in future, may help us towards a formal theory.
Step 3
Again, we would be sampling a different group to maximize group differences, but also considering further unsaturated concepts that have been discovered in Step 2, to delimit the theory and densify the theory. At this stage, one could consider sampling slices of data not from Facebook but other online sources, such as Twitter, or extending the age range further, or sampling more slices from people from various Facebook groups. Obviously, how those differences are maximized has a direct bearing on the theory development, and may also suggest new relationships between concepts. How the category of Impression Management is being filled out will suggest new avenues of theoretical sampling, until the theory is suitably densified and has adequate (theoretical) scope for the research purpose.
Note that this example gives but one route through the table, and it is a matter of judgement of how one might proceed through the table – the choice is to maximize group differences immediately, or pay attention to unsaturated concepts and deepening of the category while minimizing group differences. My own preference is for the latter, as this seems to me the best way to deepen the theory by ensuring it is grounded in lots of instances from a similar group. It's also important to note how, as we might proceed to a formal theory, the category becomes more abstract (in this example, ‘Impression Management’) and not underpinned by empirical data, as this job is done by the lower-level categories that underpin that more abstract category (in this example, ‘Curating’ and ‘Personalizing’, and no doubt many other categories). To me, the contribution of this table is not only understanding that we can extend the scope of a theory by paying attention to like and unlike groups, but that our theoretical sampling can be guided by our categories.
Levels and Scope of Theory
The previous section discussed, in detail, the guidance available from Glaser and Strauss for theory building using similar and dissimilar groups. It is helpful guidance, so, why is it not more known in the mainstream of qualitative research, and considered in numerous qualitative research textbooks consulted by graduate students? To me, the answer to this question resides in two places. First, in comparatively new disciplines, such as information systems and management, we are still unfamiliar with the process of theory building, and lack theoretical sensitivity, hence the debates on and lack of consensus on theory building in those two disciplines. Grounded theory is unique in how it encourages us to build theory systematically by use of constant comparison and theoretical sampling of groups. It also helps us understand, in detail, how theories shade into another from the substantive to the formal. So many of the newer disciplines lack a deep appreciation for the structures of theories, conveyed in grounded theory by theoretical families and the coding paradigm, and by the idea of theory mechanisms in the social sciences.
Second, by contrast, in the social sciences, there has been indeed a great deal of debate about the nature of theory, largely focused on mechanisms. However, a lot of current discussion on mechanisms tend to focus on opening up the black box, and work from higher levels of theory to lower ones4 to provide explanations. Davison and Martinsons (2016) complain about a rush to universalism in the information systems discipline, where theories borrowed from other reference disciplines are applied, regardless of the context of that application. They make a plea for the understanding and clear explication of boundary conditions when using theories, lest the context of the study be ignored. My commentary on that article (Urquhart 2016) suggested that particularism versus universalism is a false dichotomy. Grounded theorists know that Glaser (1978) states that levels of theory shade into one another as a theory becomes more and more abstracted, from substantive to formal. Stinchcombe (1991) was keenly aware of the issue of levels of theory when writing about theory mechanisms in social science. His proposition was that paying attention to lower-level mechanisms would result in a more ‘supple’ theory at the higher level. His definition of mechanisms is:
(1) a piece of scientific reasoning which is independently verifiable and gives rise to theoretical reasoning, (2) gives knowledge about a component process (generally one with units of analysis at a lower level) of another theory (ordinarily a theory with units at a different ‘higher’ level) thereby (3) increasing the suppleness, complexity, elegance or believability of the theory at a higher level without excessive multiplication of entities in that higher level theory (4) without doing too much violence (in the necessary simplification at the lower level to make the higher level go) to what we know as the main facts at the lower level. (p. 367)
This description will be immediately be recognizable to grounded theorists as a description of theoretical coding, and the need to ground those theoretical codes at the lower level, while at the same time making sure that the level of abstraction holds.
Figure 4.1 is offered as a summary of Glaser and Strauss's vision of theory building, without compromising the original vision. For me, the key insight of their approach is not that we extend the scope of the theory by sampling different groups, but that we are theoretically guided by category development as we do so.
Figure 4.1 Theory Scope and Conceptual Level

The x axis represents Conceptual Level, and the y axis Theory Scope. These are the two dimensions that are acted upon by following Glaser and Strauss's guidance on theoretical sampling. The process of sampling similar or dissimilar groups extends the scope, but it is by paying attention to saturated and unsaturated concepts that the conceptual level of the theory, and its direction, is considered and worked on.
Theory Scope
The starting point for theory building is a bounded context, where seed concepts are generated. These seed concepts might not even be empirically grounded, and little more than hunches (Urquhart, Lehmann and Myers 2010). Substantive theories, which grounded theorists are very familiar with, pertain to the specific area being investigated, but the concepts generated in that theory exist independently of that data. Formal theories focus on conceptual entities. The scope of a theory is extended by sampling like and unlike groups, guided by concepts in the data. The suggestion here too is that boundary conditions are specified for each level of theory. In grounded theory terms, these boundary conditions are represented by theoretical codes and the categories. The suggestion of Figure 4.1 (and Davison and Martinsons (2016)) is that these conditions and contexts should be clearly specified when a theory is published.
Conceptual Level
When we first begin to code data, we inevitably code descriptively as it is necessary to explain the data to ourselves. As we begin to theorize about the data, and write theoretical memos, our concepts become more analytic and less context dependent. The same applies to the relationships between concepts, where we have the challenge described by Stinchcombe (1991) of making sure the relationships we posit between concepts at the lower level also reside at the higher level.
Discussion and Conclusion
It is clear from the discussion that Glaser and Strauss did indeed have clear and systematic recommendations for theory building from 1967 onwards. One problem seems to be that, because grounded theory is seen as producing rich, qualitative theories that are about micro phenomena, these recommendations seem not have permeated into the wider academic disciplines in which we work. Layder's critique (Layder 1998) about the hopelessly detailed nature of a grounded theory, it seems, has not been fully put to rest. It is easy to see why – the very nature of the grounded theory process means we start with a very detailed and inimate relationship with the data. This is both the strength and weakness of grounded theory. The scale of the task of building a grounded theory means that we often leave it to others to then take our theories and either apply them to other contexts or test them. One possible route is to take our substantive theories and widen their scope, but the emphasis on novelty, at least in my own discipline, seems to mean that once a substantive theory is published, it cannot be elaborated upon.
That said, my observation of the newer disciplines I work with – management, information systems (IS) and software engineering – is that these disciplines often struggle with theory building and the nature of theory. Unlike my sociologist colleagues, we are largely unfamiliar with the notion of mechanisms or how formal theories are used. Grounded theory offers clear and practical guidelines on how a theory that applies to one area can be extended to another area, and also how the conceptual level of a theory can be pushed to levels of further abstraction. I would contend that newer disciplines can learn from the clarity and systematic nature of Glaser and Strauss's recommendations, because, for those disciplines, advancing new and larger theories are important. There seems to be very little discussion of levels of theory in the newer disciplines – theory is either treated as universal, generally coming from other reference disciplines, and grounded theories are not considered as contributions to the overall theory building effort. Worse, we seem to lack the language to discuss theory and theoretical contribution. In information systems, Burton-Jones, McLean andMonod (2014) make an excellent contribution to the IS theory debate when they suggests moving away from ideas of process/variance theories that are prominent in the discipline towards conceptual latitude and fit, and focusing on constructs and relationships. As Davison and Martinsons (2016) suggest, it would also be helpful if people using and advancing theories considered the context in which they were created, and the context in which they are subsequently applied. Categorizing the type of theoretical contribution could also be fruitful; for instance, Colquitt and Zapata-Phelan (2007) suggest that contributions can be categorized from those which introduce significant new concepts, and examine new relationships and processes, to those that attempt to replicate theories. They then consider to what extent that contribution is grounded, empirically or theoretically (Colquitt and Zapata-Phelan 2007).
The division between grounded theorists and their colleagues will hopefully fade as the division between qualitative and quantitative research recedes. Often, the phenomenon itself will demand a combination of quantitative and qualitative research. We need to change policies via quantitative evidence, but before we do that, we need qualitative research into what people do. The advent of Big Data and the ubiquity of social media calls for both qualitative and quantitative research – understanding patterns in data requires a qualitative understanding of why people do what they do. For too long, in my opinion, Glaser and Strauss's stellar contribution to understanding how we build theory, and how we scale up that theory, have been ignored by the mainstream of many of our academic disciplines. It is my sincere hope that this chapter contributes to interpreting the intentions of Glaser and Strauss's advice on theoretical sampling. Glaser and Strauss represent a huge intellectual contribution to theory building in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries, and these ideas can and should help theory builders everywhere.
Notes
1 Glaser and Strauss (1967) and Glaser's monograph on quantitative GT (Glaser 2008) state that grounded theories can be built from quantitative data. Walsh (2014) gives an interesting illustration of using quantitative GT in a grounded theory building process by means of cluster analysis in a mixed method study.
2 That said, Giddens’ view of his own theory has been challenged by proponents of ‘strong’ structuration theory, in, for example, Stones (2005).
3 I am indebted to Udo Kelle for this insight, and for his very helpful comments on this chapter.
4 I am indebted to my colleague Olga Volkoff for this insight.
Acknowledgements
I am very grateful to Udo Kelle, Stefan Seidel, Olga Volkoff and Hamid Pousti, all of whom gave extremely helpful comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.
References
- Loading...